水曜日, 6月 27, 2018

VALUE THEORY AND BUSINESS CYCLES 1933 MCCRACKEN




                  ( 経済学マルクスリンク::::::::::

NAMs出版プロジェクト: マルクス・カレツキ・ケインズ1933
http://nam-students.blogspot.jp/2017/04/blog-post.html
NAMs出版プロジェクト: ケインジアンの交差図 1936
http://nam-students.blogspot.jp/2015/03/blog-post_12.html
The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, The General Theory and After: A Supplement, Vol. 29: John Maynard Keynes, Elizabeth Johnson, Donald Moggridge: 洋書
https://www.amazon.co.jp/Collected-Writings-Maynard-Keynes-General/dp/1107634997/
マクラッケン
https://nam-students.blogspot.com/2018/06/blog-post_49.html

Harlan Linneus McCracken
Published by Falcon Press, USA (1933)
https://books.google.co.jp/books?redir_esc=y&hl=ja&id=rvOSZG3_BoQC&q=marx#v=snippet&q=marx&f=false
p.41~56 Chapter 3 Karl Marx



VALUE THEORY AND BUSINESS CYCLES
Chapter 3 KARL MARX

46:

VALUE THEORY AND BUSINESS CYCLES

ond, labor being used less would be able to buy back less, hence

demand would drop off. (To this extent Marx departed from

an embodied labor theory to that of demand and supply. In

fact, embodied value theorists unwittingly pass over to a demand

and supply analysis with more or less frequency.)


THE BUSINESS CYCLE AND SURPLUS VALUE

Clearly for Marx, the secular trend was downward. But in

addition to a secular trend, he sought also to establish the fact

of a constantly recurring business cycle. The theory of the

cycle or of crises was based wholly upon his Surplus Value

analysis. Surplus Value holds so important a place in the general

theory of Marx that it is necessarv to study it with care.

In dealing with exchange or the metamorphosis of commodities, he first treated C-M-C [Commodity for Money for Commodity]. Such an exchange he considered no different in principle from that of barter since the object of exchange was to

transfer a commoditv of little or no utility to its possessor for

a different commodity of high utility, and money entered as a

convenient medium to effect the transaction. This double transaction indicated no exploitation, for the assumption was that in

each transaction there was an exchange of equivalent values, or

quantities of embodied labor, so the final commodity had

neither more nor less value than the original commodity, but

had a higher utility for the recipient. Thus the metamorphosis

C-M-C represented an exchange of equivalent values and no

exploitation. Marx admitted the possibility of variation in value,

but such would be accidental and negligible and not inherent in

the process.

But the metamorphosis M-C-M' was fundamentallv different. And it was in explaining this formula that Marx treated

thoroughly the nature and source of surplus value. In this case

the individual starts with money and ends with money. The only

possible motive, then, for making the two exchanges was to end

with more money than at the beginning. And the extent to which

the second M or M' exceeds the first, is the measure of surplus value.  

47:

However, surplus value was not created or gained in

the circulation of commodities but in production. The first M

represented the money paid to labor for wages. In return for

the wages received labor created commodities C which belonged

to the employer, the value being determined by the amount of

labor-time or social labor-power incorporated. Then Marx, in

the inimitable Marxian style, proceeded to show that, whereas

there was an exchange of equivalents as between commodities,

vet with the concentration of capital and tools into the hands

of capitalists and the rise of the proletariat, divorced from tools

and compelled to seek employment of the capitalist, there arose

a transaction between employer and laborer, a transaction in

volving the exchange of labor-power for subsistence, in which

case there was no guarantee whatsoever that there would be an

exchange of equivalents, but rather a predetermined certainty

that labor would invest more social labor-power than would be

returned as wages

Marx then turned directly to an analysis of the determination of wages. "We must now examine more closely this peculiar commodity, labor-power. Like all others, it has its value.

How is that value determined?"

Value of Labor-Power Determined by Cost of Subsistence

and Perpetuation

"The value of labor-power is determined as in the case of every

other commodity by the labor-time necessary for the production, and

also for the reproduction of this special article. So far as it has value,

it represents no more than a definite quantity of the average labor

of society incorporated in it. Labor-power exists only as a capacity, or

power of the living individual. Its production, consequently, presup-

poses his existence. Given the individual, the production of labor-

power consists in his reproduction of himself or his maintenance. For

his maintenance he required a given quantity of the means of subsistence. Therefore the labor-time requisite for the production of

labor-power reduces itself to that necessarv for the production of those

means of subsistence; in other words the value of labor-power is the

value of the means of subsistence necessary for the maintenance of the

laborer. .. . His means of subsistence must therefore be sufficient

to maintain him in his normal state as a laboring individual. 


48:

His natural wants such as food, clothing, fuel and housing vary according

to the climatic, and other physical conditions of his country. On the

other hand the number and extent of his so-called necessary wants, as

also the modes of satisfying them, are themselves the product of his-

torical development, and depend therefore to a great extent on the

degree of civilization of a country, more particularly on the condi-

tion under which, and consequently on the habits and degree of com

fort in which, the class of free laborers has been formed. In contra-

distinction therefore to the case of other commodities, there enters

into the determination of the value of labor-power a historical and

moral element. Nevertheless in a given country at a given period the

average quantity of the means of subsistence necessary for the laborer

is practically known. .

into the value of a definite quantity of the means of subsistence. It

therefore varies with the value of the means or with the quantity of

labor requisite for their production." 6

The value of labor-power resolves itself

Thus we are led to see that Marx held that the wages of labor

were determined, not by the amount of social labor-power which

they invested in commodities for their employers, but by the cost

of maintenance which tended to hover around the subsistence

level, though it might be modified upwards slightly by the pre-

vailing standard of living. It was by showing that labor actually

did embodv more labor-power in the commoditv which it cre-

ated for emplovers than was embodied in the monev which it

received as wages that employers found themselves the pos-

sessors of commodities more valuable than their cost. This rep-

resented surplus value created bv labor, for 'which it received no

equivalent.

Returning to a final analysis of the formula M-C-M' the employer possessed a certain quantity of money, which represented

so much embodied or crystallized social labor-power. With this

he employed workmen who, in exchange, created for him the C

of the equation or so many commodities in which was embodied

a quantity of social labor-power, which, as we have already observed, might hold little or no relation to the value of money

which he gave for its production and tended on the average to be far in excess. 

6 Marx, Capital, Vol. I, pp. 189-91

49:

This C of the equation was then sold on the

market at its full value in exchange for a quantity of money of

exactly equivalent value, i.e., embodying the same amount of

crvstallized social labor-power. By the extent to which the

quantity and value of the second M exceeded that of the first, by

so much had surplus value been created by labor. It also represented the exact extent to which labor had been exploited.

As has been said, the wages of labor were determined, by

the cost of subsistence, or of production and reproduction. The

employer therefore paid him a sufficient money wage to guaran-

tee that subsistence. But upon payment of that wage, the capital

ist laid claim to the full productive capacity of the worker. To

illustrate mathematicallv, if labor in six hours embodied value

in commodities equivalent to that contained in the specie re-

ceived as wages, but the employer withheld the specie until an

additional six hours of labor-power had been embodied, then it

is clear that labor has created six hours of surplus value for the

employer for which no equivalent was paid. This represented

accurately the degree of exploitation of labor, and Marx called

it "surplus value."7

But exploitation has its limits and cannot go on indefinitely

without producing serious maladjustments in the commodity

field. All commodities produced must be exchanged (or vir-

tually all in modern capitalistic economy) and the only effective

demand is the supply of another commodity, the value of which

is proportionate to the labor-power embodied. But the greatest

group of buyers, or consumers is comprised of the laboring class

which has been "robbed" of part of its purchasing power, hence

it cannot buy back the product of its labor. Commodities seek a

market but can find none, or if they do, they must seek it at a

market price much below the actual or market value. Then both

entrepreneurs and labor lose, the former becomes bankrupt and

the latter unemploved because factories close down and the world

experiences a crisis. Indeed it comes at the time when the supply

of commodities is the greatest. While the occasion for the crisis

7 Marx, Capital, Vol. I, pp. 197-215


50:

was bankruptcy of entrepreneurs, the basic cause was in the ex-

ploitation of labor through employers' extortion of surplus value.

If the cause of crises was to be found in underpavment of

workers, with consequent lack of market for goods, a glut of the

market and bankruptcy of employers, how was recovery to come

about? The crisis was caused by too much goods, not only con-

sumption goods, but also capital goods; in other words the

powers of production had outrun the power of effective demand

or consumption, and a bottomed market resulted.

But all above the dire poverty line kept on consuming fairly

normally even in time of depression. Ultimately the glut was

worked off, because factories were closed down and production

had ceased. Also, many bankrupt firms were unable to start

again, machinery rusted away, factories were abandoned, etc. In

other words the function of depression was to scrap enough

capital goods so that the powers of production no longer ex-

ceeded those of consumption, ie.) consumption goods became

scarce, market price came back to market value, which always

contained a margin of profit, hence industries started up with a

vim and the cycle started on its first phase again, but only to

run the gamut of the previous cycle

Thus about the downward secular trend, there ran constantly

this cyclical curve of prosperity, glut, bankruptcy, crisis, and

depression; all based in the last analysis on "surplus value ex-

ploitation.'"

Thus far, we have attempted to show how Marx explained

the secular trend of the price level on the basis of embodied

value, and the cyclical movement of market prices on the basis

of surplus value. Standing alone each explanation seems logical

and complete. The difficulty arises when we attempt to reconcile

the two. If the value of commodities was determined bv the

amount of labor embodied, how could goods sell at times far

below this value, as at the time of crisis, and at other times far

above their value as in the period of prosperity?

Marx noted the apparent contradiction and promised a recon-

ciliation at a later time. 


51:

This was eagerly looked for in the second

volume of "Das Kapital" but strangely, it was conspicuous by its

absence. However, before his death the attempt had been made

and Engels found it among his manuscripts, and published it in

Volume III.8

Stripped of its verbiage, numerous definitions and involved

formulae, Marx held that two sets of forces were operating in

the determination of value and market price. The fundamental

and primary force, was embodied social labor-power. This de-

termined the value of all commodities. (Value here is used in ex-

actly the same way in which Ricardo used "Natural Value.") The

natural value of commodities was determined by the quantitv of

labor embodied, and market price would never depart from this

unless influenced by some disturbing factor. The disturbing factor

was found in "Demand and Supply" which constituted a secondary

force. But demand and supply had no effect so long as they were in

equilibrium. Furthermore, demand would always equal supply

if labor were not exploited. If it could buy back the full volume

of its product the market would never become glutted and

therefore market price would be held constantly at the natural

value. But due to the exploitation of labor, the compulsory pro-

duction of surplus value, supply exceeded demand and when de-

mand and supply were not in equilibrium, they did have an effect

upon prices and compelled market price to depart from the curve

of Natural Value.


In the words of Marx:

"If demand and supply balance, then they cease to have any effect,

and for this very reason commodities are sold at their market values.

If two forces exert themselves equally in opposite directions, they

balance one another, they have no influence at all on the outside,

and any phenomena taking place at the same time must be explained

by other causes than the influence of these forces. If demand and sup

ply balance one another, they cease to explain anything, they do not

affect market values and therefore leave us .. . in the dark. . . .

It is evident that the essential fundamental laws of production can-

not be explained by the interaction of supply and demand. . . . For

these laws cannot be observed in their pure state until the effects of

8 See Marx, Capital, Vol. III, Ch. X